Welcome to Randal Douc's wiki

A collaborative site on maths but not only!

User Tools

Site Tools


world:boule

This is an old revision of the document!


Table of Contents

Question

Let $D$ be an infinite set without accumulation points in $\mathbb{R}^d$. Show that, for every $n \in \mathbb{N}^*$, there exists a ball containing exactly $n$ points of $D$.

Proof

First, note that $D$ must be countable. Indeed, for each point $x \in D$, one can associate a *rational ball* (that is, a ball with rational center coordinates and rational radius) containing $x$ as the only element of $D$. This defines an injection from $D$ into the countable set of rational balls, which proves that $D$ is countable.

Now consider, for $(a,b) \in D \times D$, the affine hyperplane $$ H_{a,b} = \{ x \in \mathbb{R}^d \; ; \; \|x-a\| = \|x-b\| \}. $$

Define $$ G = \bigcup_{a,b \in D} H_{a,b}. $$

Since $G$ is a countable union of closed sets with empty interior, it still has empty interior by Baire’s theorem. Therefore, $G$ cannot be the whole $\mathbb{R}^d$. We can choose a point $c \in \mathbb{R}^d \setminus G$.

The distances $\|c-x\|$ for $x \in D$ are then all distinct. Define $$ A = \{ \|c-x\| \; ; \; x \in D \}. $$

To order these distances strictly, it is enough to check that, for every $r>0$, the set $A \cap [0,r]$ is finite. But $A \cap [0,r]$ corresponds to the number of points in $D \cap B(c,r)$, which is a compact set containing no accumulation points. Hence it is finite.

We can thus write $A = \{\rho_n \; ; \; n \geq 1\}$ with $\rho_n$ strictly increasing. For every $n \geq 1$, by choosing a radius $\rho$ such that $\rho_n < \rho < \rho_{n+1}$, the ball $B(c,\rho)$ contains exactly $n$ points of $D$.


Remarks:

  • One can avoid Baire’s theorem by using a measure-theoretic argument. Let $\lambda_d$ be the Lebesgue measure on $\mathbb{R}^d$. Since $\lambda_d(H_{a,b})=0$, we get $\lambda_d(\bigcup_{a,b \in D} H_{a,b})=0$. Hence $\bigcup_{a,b \in D} H_{a,b} \neq \mathbb{R}^d$.
  • For $D = \mathbb{Z}^d$, one can construct $c$ explicitly, for example $c=(\pi,\ldots,\pi^d)$. Then, for $a,b \in \mathbb{Z}^d$, the equality $\|c-a\|^2=\|c-b\|^2$ becomes a polynomial equation with integer coefficients having $\pi$ as a root. This is impossible unless $a=b$, since $\pi$ is not algebraic. However, this explicit construction of $c$ does not generalize (or at least not simply) when $D$ is not $\mathbb{Z}^d$.
  • Obviously, when $D = \mathbb{Z}^d$, one does not need to prove that $D$ is countable, nor that $A \cap [0,r]$ is finite, which significantly shortens the proof.
world/boule.1759449495.txt.gz · Last modified: 2025/10/03 01:58 by rdouc